20051006.00 Structure of Scientific Revolutions - 1 Thomas Kuhn's book, which I have read in a desultory manner, has become the nidus of my reflections about epistemology, about the discontinuity between public and private knowledge, about science as communal as distinct from individual knowledge. Universal knowledge exists in the mind of God. Indeed, the need for a repository of knowledge is one of the main reasons why God must be discovered or invented. The presumptions of science preclude the concept of private knowledge. It does not arise. By definition, anything that I can know must also be intelligible to and knowable by (any) other human beings in a manner identical to that with which I know. The quality of scientific knowledge is not dependent on the person who posesses it, is not dependent on the knower. Awkward though it sounds, it must be said that hypothetically, anything known by others is knowable also by me, at least potentially. Practically, of course, my knowledge is only a fraction, and a very small one, of the universal knowledge which historically has been ascribed to the mind of God. But before going further, it is perhaps worthwhile to point out that questions such as these can be considered only in the light of at least a tentative determination of what knowledge is. It may prove to be a useful functional definition of science vs non-science, that science purports to be communal knowledge, and relegates cognition that is not communal, or to the extent that it is not communal, to the categories of non-science, poetry, fiction, fantasy. However, this definition entails obvious and pressing problems: 1) A scientific assertion begins with a communal postulate, but ends, inevitably, with private intuition. Indeed the process of becoming scientific, of acquiring scientific knowledge, may be described as the subjectification of objective knowledge, as the transformation of objective into subjective knowledge; e.g. the ability to solve a differential equation is clearly subjective: the validity of the solution, however, is objective. 2) There is a propensity, an innate necessity for the individual to give to his subjective intuitive experience objective expression. Most primitive the guffaw of laughter, the ouch of pain. Linguistic expression, language is the transformation of feeling into an objective construct; and conversely, listening hearing, reading is the assimilation of the objective construct into subjectivity. 3) Science is the disciplined translation of subjective experience into objective representation. The giving of directions, the drawing of a map is a simple example. But the directions, the map are never totally accurate; the directions are ever subject to misinterpretation. To be applied, they must be subjectively assimilated. 4) The discipline of science is far from absolute; if it were, scientific knowledge would be ultimately conclusive, would not be subject to emendation or improvement. Many instances may be cited where the discipline of science was insufficient, was unable, was incapable of filtering out the subjective elements, whose translations into valid objectivity were spurious or failed altogether. Indeed closely examined: a) all scientific truth contains elements of subjectivity. b) objectivity is an ideal which is never achieved. c) fictions can also become objective, in that they are accepted as subject to demonstration and proof. Consider both secular, and most importantly, religious mythology. If epistemology is not about science, there is no point to it. For if epistemology is about anything at all, it is about knowledge; and in our culture, in our language, science is knowledge, purportedly science is the real knowledge, the only knowledge. That, of course, may or may not be true, may, in the end turn out to be a falsehood. But meanwhile it will be necessary to ask what we mean by scientific knowledge; and if it means less than we thought, then to redefine what we mean by science, or to free ourselves to go on to something more valid. But in no case, in no event, can we afford to ignore what passes as science. Kuhn has rendered a substantial service by identifying normal science as distinct from scientific innovation. The extent to which the paradigm of natural science has preempted our intellectual lives, intellectual existence, the notion of positive philosophy promoted by Auguste Comte. or John Stuart Mill, writing about "Moral Sciences", on the implicit premise that science was all there was, that to be meaningful everything had to be integrated into, had to be interpreted in the light of (natural) science; even history, literature and art. The same, of course was Wilhelm Dilthey's premise. But given the reliance on technology, the extent to which technology supports, controls, governs our lives, isn't it absurd to the point of dishonesty to argue otherwise, to deprecate or deny the validity of science? In the end this argument, like all others, proves to be an argument about words. To argue about, to challenge, to deny the conventional image (view) of science is far from denying science itself, it is merely asking what that science is, what that science accomplishes and how that science accomplishes what it does. What is denied is the conventional interpretation of the way science develops and the way science works. What is necessary (essential) is not the upholding of the conventional view of science, Kuhn's, Conant's or anyone elses. All that is necessary is a clear understanding of the forces (factors, determinants) of our contemporary lives, by whatever names we call them. But even that may be too pretentious. All I should try to do is to consider just what the specific scientific knowledge is that I may rely on as I sit here in this chair at 12:30 a.m. on October 12. 2005. As if I were sitting down for an examination, and the question were asked of me, What do you know; and I recounted what I knew of what I thought I knew ... making some provision for what I have forgotten. Compte's, Mill's and Dilthey's efforts in regard to moral sciences or Geisteswissenschaften are of course only as valid, cogent as the concept of natural science, as the reality of natural science, as natural science itself. An interesting way of looking at (reading) Kuhn's book is to see the sense in which, rather than interpreting history as science, he interprets science as history, (although he doesn't know it). The divergence of moral and natural sciences is ultimately untenable. There is obviously a point which neither Dilthey nor Kuhn reach, where the roots of natural and moral science coincide or converge in the nature of the human mind, or in the nature of the world, or in the nature of both. And that is the point toward which I am aiming, whether I reach it or not is another matter. Neither individual nor communal knowledge can be projected - or reduced - to unambiguous limits. That whose limit are blurred is undefined, What is undefined is unknown, and what is undefinable is unknowable. Individual knowledge is ultimately unidentifiable because the subjective consciousness in which that knowledge inheres is intangible and undefinable and because individual knowledge is inconceivable as separate from the community, e.g. the phenomenon of language. But communal knowledge is unidentifiable in an analogous manner, if only because the textbook or encyclopedia is, by its nature, never conclusive or definitive. The scientific textbook, since knowledge is in flux, can never be "up to date". Even more important: Even the textbook which purports to be inexorably objective, will unavoidably require to be read, to be interpreted, to be understood, to be explained, will, in other words, require subjective interpretation. Human science is no more accessible to us than the course of fishes in the ocean or the flight of birds through the air. Only the parameters are accessible to us. Thus, at the foundation of his argument, Kuhn must gloss over the unidentifiability of knowledge. To proceed at all, Kuhn must postulate an entity that is known, a commodity transferable by formula and by text. This postulate is the prerequisite to Kuhn's other assumptions, specifically to the notion of the paradigm as a framework or pattern of identified knowledge. The postulate of idwentified knowledge leads into an uncharted, and in fact unchartable ocean of scholastic speculation. This lapse into unmanageable scholasticism can be avoided only by disciplined cognitive abstinence: in the Socratic spirit of being willing to confront the circumstance that one knows nothing. Such abstinence may be accompanied by a careful and conscientious account and description of what it is that one may claim to know, and an account of how the legitimate claim to some knowledge predictably and unavoidably mushrooms into clouds of cognitive fantasy. It is actually a most difficult enterprise to maintain the assertion of ones ignorance in more than a superficial way. In the end, it is more difficult to be come to terms with not knowing, and to understand what not knowing means than to maintain the proficiency in some cognitive paradigm a proficiency that will inevitably be superficial, that presents itself (masquerades) as knowledge. Valid knowledge is not knowledge of facts but proficiency in action, is not in making statements but in pursuing paths; not inventing concepts but discovering traversable avenues of thought. Knowledge as mental skill. All knowledge may be understood in terms of two rubrics: history and skill: what I can say: what I can make immediate, present by saying, describing, relating it, representing it in words, sentences, picture or melody; and what I can do: and my skills, my ability, to alter my world or to make my way through it, to thread my path through its labyrinth. More closely scrutinized, the two facets of knowledge coincide after all: Knowing that some is or is not so, the ability to tell a story, to give an account is an expression of memory: and memory is the ability to remember, the "can do" of mental representation. By the same token, the ability to find ones way home, the ability to circumnavigate the globe or to set foot on the moon is but an alternate, and logically equivalent mode of stating the geographical and engineering specifications which make these accomplishments possible. THe interconvertibility and the ability to interconvert one mode of knowledge to the other is integral to scientific culture. Kuhn's error is his functional denial of the subjectivity of knowledge. his failure to account for, to describe, to give an account of the subjective experience of science. The key to epistemology is reflection and elucidation of what it is that actually happens (to, in me) when I perform a scientifically relevant or meaningful act. In this connection, the history of science hold a special place because of the implicit claim of science to truth that endures. The truth of a non-scientific political or social event is limited to the time of its occurrence. The truth of a scientific event, of the scientific paradigm which plays so prominent a role in Kuhns thinking is assumed to have no temporal limits. A previous assumption of mine was that when I understood of a scientific fact or event I in fact elaborated a mind set, an understanding, a pattern of thought which mimicked that of the original situation: but I no longer think this is (necessarily) the case. I still agree that such imitation, such mimicking may be a good analogy, but it remains that, because quite realistically, the original situation/event in its uniqueness cannot be reached or even approximated. I must satisfy myself with the recognition that all my reflection is an approximation, an imitation, and can never be more, and to some extent is actually a synthesis, separate and distinct from that which it purports to exhaust. The conclusive element, the bottom line so to speak, is the community of understanding, of intent, of purpose, of action which the scientific presumption creates. It is not that my understanding approximates that of Copernicus, Newton, Lavoisier, Maxwell or Einstein, but that their theories, my - our - understanding, interpretation of their thought creates and provides a point of reference for futher action, both conceptual, theoretical and practical. History is the recitation of a story, is a telling of what one remembers, a revelation, an unveiling of what is in memory, eine Veraeusserung des Geistes. The subjective truth of history is what passes through one mind, what one thinks as one tell the (hi)story, THe what is the book, the history book, the text. It is a composition, a synthesis, an invention. It is something which is constructed or made. Surely memory goes into the making of the book; memory went into the composition of Homeric epics. Memory enters into what I write (and read) in a recursive way. I read what I have written, or what someone else has written, or I hear a story told, and this experience stimulates my mind in two ways: I remember what I read; but what I read also elicits and modifies my memories. And I think there is no fundamental difference betweens the effect on memory of a scientific and a non-scientific text. The ability to solve a mathematical problem. This is also an expression of memory. The difference between memory and other mental functions. It is an error to treat science as a commodity.xs, as something that can be elaborated, converyed or understood independent of the individual who interprets or elaborates it. independent of the individual who acts in consequence or in conformity with it. Knowledge in general and scientific knowledge in particular must be understood as integral to the individual who entertains, expresses, utilizes or conveys it. Such an interpretation will, in itself, resolve the incongruity of subjective objective knowledge; the inherences (Innewohnen) of knowledge in the person will in itself express the dual characteristic of knowledge as being both individual and communal. Characteristic of the history of science, of the description of science, as of the content (burden) of science itself is the process (phenomenon) of completion, of filling in and extending experience with the concepts that describe it. The concepts supplement and extend the experience, while at the same time proving themselves unable to exhaust experience. Hence it is our nature to presume to know what we do not, what we cannot know. That is the psychological basis of the Socratic admonition against the presumption of knowledge. Ultimately one cannot write _about_ science. One cannot deal with science as if it were a commodity. One can appropriate science only by assimilating it. One can appropriate science only by becoming, by being a scientist. Thus the suspicion of scientists about epistemology, about philosophy is validated; the rejection of epistemology and philosophy is validated. Such considerations appear to confirm the validity of the Hippocratic method of medicine, which spurns theory and rhetoric but relies on the physician'ss first hand (immediate) experience of diseases quite unconsciously to shape his judgment. If scientific knowledge were not over extensive, it would be incomprehensible. The fragments of "truth" would be so small and so scattered that they could not be assimilated, interpreted or understood. The solution to the problem of epistemology, if it is a problem, is that it must be a study of how we think. It can be nothing but introspective. We cannot study, we cannot observe, we cannot perceive how anyone else thinks, we have no access to a foreign mental process. I can understand only the science which is familiar to me. I can understand science only to the extent that I am a scientist. My understanding of science can never be a substitute to my being a scientist myself. But arguably my being a scientist myself subsumes the need to understand science. For I cannot be a scientist without understanding science. It is certainly plausible to argue that introspective analysis of thought of thinking, of science is not enough, is inadequate; but if this is the case, then we have no alternative but to abandon the quest. * * * * *

Zurueck

Weiter

2005 Index

Website Index

Copyright 2005, Ernst Jochen Meyer