20060614.00 Embers makes explicit the contradictions that potentially inhere in all relationships of love or friendship, and demonstrates the proximity of love and hate, of friendship and enmity. It is a mistake to assume that friendship or love are functions of the will. No one is able to "decide" whether and in what degree and in what manner he/she should "love" or "hate" another individual. In this perspective the Christian admonitions "Love thy neighbor" is fatally misleading, implying as it does that love might be something which one can choose or reject. If it is there, it will not be quenched. If not, it cannot be subpoened or conjured up. Love arises from the subject's need, be it physical, emotional or intellectual, for another individual. Hate is the expression of the subject's need to preserve his/her own identity in the face of encroachment by the other person. Usually love and friendship enhance and stengthen the identity of the loved person; however, on occasion, and perhaps more frequently than one recognizes, they may also threaten and prejudice that identity, thus paradoxically giving rise to hate: and this, I think is what Marai describes in his novel. And, appearances to the contrary, it is not Konrad who hates Henrik, - perhaps he does, but Konrad's hate, if it exists, is not displayed in the novel. It is Henrik, the General, who hates Konrad; and says as much in his monologue. The real issue in Marai's Embers is not whether Krisztina and Konrad plotted to murder Henrik (the General). Is not even the nature of the relationship between Konrad and Henrik, be it of love or hate. The over-arching question raised by the novel: what is reality, what is truth? And the answer is obscure. I read Embers as a latter day expression of a Kantian argument, a variation on Kant's teaching about transcendental apperception, which insists, in Kierkegaard's words that subjectivity is the truth, and in Schopenhauer's that the world is my idea. If Embers had been an ordinary detective story, the point of the tale would have been the ingenious discovery of "the smoking gun," providing the logical legal proof that a crime had been committed. In the story of Embers, however, we have proof, eloquent and interminable to the point of ennui, that the crime of murder, at least, has not been committed: The 75 year old General, hosting his friend-enemy Konrad, is very much alive. Perhaps the moral of this chronicle should be not that Konrad was so evil as to plot to murder Henrik, but the contravening hypothesis that Konrad's diligence in fact saved Henrik's life, - let us say, by Konrad's dropping his gun when Henrik inadvertently interposed himself into the line of fire. Consider the precept of Jesus: 28 but I say unto you, That whosoever looketh on a woman to lust after her hath committed adultery with her already in his heart. (Matthew 5) Surely what is true of lust is true of murder. The General argues that murder is also susceptible of being perpetrated in the heart; and that the exclamation which rings everywhere in our ears: "I'm so angry, I could kill him!" or even "I could kill you!", is not so innocuous, as we, careless and insensitive in our speech, have come to assume. That Konrad on more than one occasion might have had hostile feelings, might have thought to himself, or even said to Krisztina, "I could kill Henrik" is not only plausible: it is almost certain. Such feelings are human, very human, and bringing their significance to light, is one of the corollary virtues of this novel. The indictment is a legal issue, and if it is to me brought, must be precise. Contrary to Henrik's assertion, a thought, an intention is never a crime, at least in secular jurisprudence. The crime would have been conspiracy, which as the semantics of the word indicate, requires the cooperation of two or more individuals. There is no suggestion that Krisztina ever did or said anything to aid or abet the hypothetically murderous encounter. So much for the charge of murder, reduced to a charge of murderous intent, and this charge in turn reduced further to the charge of murderous thoughts, a charge to be summarily dismissed. The Biblical citation: 28 but I say unto you, That whosoever looketh on a woman to lust after her hath committed adultery with her already in his heart. (Matthew 5) obviously is pertinent also to the supposedly adulterous bond between Konrad and Krisztina. Because given the situation in which Konrad and Krisztina found themselves, it is inconceivable that they should not, on occasion, have felt drawn to each other. The threshold beyond which conventional, socially acceptable affection becomes lust, beyond which friendship becomes adultery, the boundary, in other words, between philia and eros, is a shadowy no man's land, a danger zone, that is in reality undefinable and remains forever uncertain. Indeed, I find the lawyers' efforts to define what constitutes sexual intimacy, a definition indispensable if the activity is to be punished, unspeakably crude and vulgar, and I give it wide berth, even at the cost of foregoing some interesting argument. So, how should one define adultery. Surely an occasional exchange of letters or social courtesies won't won't fill the bill. The degree of intellectual, emotional or physical intimacy required to reach the threshold of adultery remains forever uncertain. Perhaps under the most critical examination the term adultery loses much, if not all of its meaning. I mention it to emphasize that the world in which Marai places the General, Krisztina and Konrad, is not all that different from the world which we too inhabit. To my mind, the evidence, so preposterously obvious, that Konrad's murder was not even an intent, was nothing more than the thought, persuades me to the conviction that Krisztina's adultery was similarly fantasy only. I find no evidence at all to the contrary. And that is the whole point: what is real, what is compelling to us is not some objective world outside of us. What is real and compelling is what we think, is what is in - what is on - our minds. The spoken and the written word, and more generally the symbolic intellectual interchanges which constitute our community of reason, and indeed the entirety of our intellectual culture, "scientific" as well as "humanistic", this is what we recognize and understand as reality. The ultimate value of Embers is that it reminds us of the ultimately subjective nature of truth. It seems to me very much worthwhile to read this book as an exercise in philosophy or more specifically, in epistemology. Given the General's definition of friendship as an experience that could not be expunged by hate, even by murder, there is a remarable contrast between Henrik's treatment of Konrad and his treatment of Kristina. While he waited 41 years for Konrad's return, he absented himself from Krizstina immediately subsequent to the crisis, and would have no contact with her for the eight remaining years of her life. That contrast surely says something compelling and conclusive about the difference between the two relationships. Under the circumstances, is it conceivable that the General, all professions of affection notwithstanding, did not love his wife, but hated her? The ambiguity of love and friendship, their proximity to hate and enmity, is everywhere visible in human relations, - family relations especially. The General believed that during the 24 years of their "friendship", Konrad hated him, but that he cherished Konrad as a friend. To the extent that the General's argument of unextinguishable friendship is valid, the General's determination so eloquently expressed at their Last Supper, to punish Konrad and to hurt him, suggests that it was the General who hated, and that it may have been Konrad who loved. * * * * *

Zurueck - Back

Weiter - Next

2006 Index

Website Index

Copyright 2006, Ernst Jochen Meyer