20080527.00 History and Mathematics Between history and mathematics there are differences with far-reaching implications. History is my recapitulation of the past. Fundamentally, history is my story of my memory of what I have seen and heard and felt, in short, what I have experienced.(erlebt) My memory is notoriously feeble, fragile and unreliable. Mathematics is a skill that I acquire and cultivate by practice. It entails no memory of the past. I can have no memory of what I have not experienced, - but I can hear and read the accounts of the experiences of others, and vicariously make these experiences my own. To be able to tell the story of other persons, I must share their experiences, if only vicariously. To purport to tell the stories of other persons is to claim the vicarious sharing of their experiences. That is the function of the historian. All history is of the past. Even "current events" are past events. Their currency is always only relative. When I report what I am "presently" experiencing, I am, strictly speaking, reporting about the past. The present, if it exists at all, is left behind in the processes of consciousness and communication. The present is an illusion: it is a consequence (an expression, a reflection) of the vividness and force of recent memory. All memory is of the past, all memory is fleeting, fallible and incomplete; so is all knowledge of the past. Memory is an echo, a recapitulation of a prior original mental state. That original mental state is but an inference, for in and of itself the original mental state is inaccessible. Even the initial awareness of that original mental state is already a memory. My knowledge of myself, my story of myself, my history of myself, is a chain of progressively attenuated memories. I tell my story in words, by means of language. There is no other method or mechanism of substantive communication. The words themselves, the story itself, becomes a subject of memory. I remember not only the original experience. I remember also my account, my story, my history of it. The memory of the account merges with and often largely masks the memory of the original experience. The elements that enter into my present memory fuse and become indistinguishable. I tell my (hi)story to others and they tell their (hi)stories to me. The histories fuse and the elements of the combined histories become indistinguishable. There develops then a very large and complex body of accounts of the past, i.e. of memories of uncounted individuals, documented in thousands of books, massive and impermeable to analysis. This accretion and concatenation appears to take on a reality of its own, independent of the memory of any given individual. We henceforth think and speak as if the cumulative histories made the past accessible to us. But this accessibility is an illusion. History, the story that we tell each other, remains rooted only in fragile and evanescent memory. Discipline, especially academic discipline, will nurture and enforce a certain uniformity of account and interpretation; and the consistency of accounts and stories will seem to vouch for their validity and truth. Yet it can easily be demonstrated that the objective validity and truth seemingly vouched for by consistency are only relative, subject to revision, rescission and correction. Dilthey's claim of validity for the historical "sciences" notwithstanding, The bounds of history are undefinable in practice as well as in theory. dependent as they are on individual memory and individual experience (Erleben). Their objective truth is always only an approximation. Their real truth is subjective; it inheres in the imagery and drama that they evoke in the mind of the historian, imagery and drama that is peculiar to each re-teller of the history, Nonetheless, the "objective" truth of historical statements is of great practical importance, as exemplified by the sworn testimony of the witness in a court of law. The objective truth or falsehood of historical statements requires to be reconciled with the insight that history is always deficient and incomplete. The crux here is that subjective truth derives from its passionate reflection and expression of experience, whereas objective truth reflects the consistency of statements, is therefore a logical, hence a mathematical truth. Another way of considering this is to note that if subjective truth is the correspondence of the account with the experience there can also be subjective falsehood when the account does not correspond to the experience; and while experience is admittedly and assertedly subjective, the subjective accounts of (other) witnesses to the same (given) event will also shed light on the subjective and objective veracity of any given account. The "memory" on which mathematics relies is fundamentally and radically different from historical memory. Mathematics knows no past; it is practiced in an eternal present. It knows no past. Although mathematics can, and does rise (develop) to extraordinary complexity which is far beyond me, I content myself with reflecting on the simplest of mathematical procedures, counting, addition, subtraction, multiplcation division of natural numbers, the simple operations of algebra and analytic geometry. Implicitly assuming that there is no fundamental qualitative difference between the epistemological significance of the simplest mathematical operations and the most complex. If I am wrong, an author more sophisticated than I will have to discover and define these differences. All the mathematics that I know (understand) entails the assimilation into intellect and the expression thereafter as spontaneous intellectual (mental) function of what is intuitively obvious or becomes intuitively obvious with suitable demonstration. The difference between those of us mathematically talented and those of us not mathematically talented, as myself, is the facility of intuition. And indeed it is arguable whether there might not be some mathematicians with intuition overly open to novelty, to whom seems obvious what no one else is able to understand. But this is an issue which does not require to be broached in this context. What does matter is that neither the mathematical intuition nor its formal integration into (mathematical) thought, although like all other experience, it occurs in time, is an historical event. I.e. the historical circumstance of its discovery and assimilation, the name of the teacher or the textbook, the date and circumstance of the lecture, are all irrelevant to its meaning. The correctness of our counting, addition, subtraction, etc, is independent of the occsions on which we do so, and independent also of the occasions on which we learned. The skill that we have acquired has become an integral component of our mental function, no less compelling, and ultimately qualitatively indistinguishable from a language that we have learned to speak or a musical instrument that we have learned to play. These considerations open yet another dimension the analysis of which we need not pursue. While it is the dominant symbolism of both mathematics and language which makes them unhistorical, there are important differences between mathematics and language in respect to the relationship of each to experience. The reality which mathematics reflects and to which mathematics makes its appeal is an element of our mental constitution as intellectual individuals. The reality which language reflects and to which language makes its appeal is an element of our social constitution as intellectual community. I propose that the validity (truth) of mathematics is its objectivity, while the validity (truth) of history is its subjectivity. One does not have to accept Kierkegaard's assertion that subjectivity is the only truth, to acknowledge that subjectivity entails elements of truth peculiar to it. As I cannot conceive of telling a story independent of memory, so I cannot conceive of the history of anything whatsoever independent of the memory of the individual who purports to tell - or to write an historical account. All history shares the qualities of memory, its evanescence and its incompleteness. Every story is dependent on the memory and hence on the experience of the individual who tells it. Academic history, no matter how abstract and defined, cannot escape the dependence on memory and on experience. The memory entailed in mathematics is so different that it requires to be distinguished by a different name. Training in mathematics is training to think by rote, independent of memory, to recapitulate without reflection, patterns of symbols by which thought is henceforth defined and controlled. The truth of mathematics derives from the power which such symbols exercise in defining and controlling thought. The truth of mathematics is the predictable uniformity which in turn makes it indispensable in constructing the network of unambiguous statements that constitutes the ideal, if not the actual achievement of natural science. As mathematical sciences are in theory invariably definable, so historical "sciences", notwithstanding Dilthey, are in theory invariably undefinable, dependent as they are on individual memory and individual experience (Erleben). Their "truth" is the imagery and drama, peculiar to each re-teller of the history, that they evoke in the mind of the historian. Admittedly, both terms, history and mathematics, serve as acronyms, as summarizing definitions for much broader fields; for fields so broad that I can only sketch their extent. It is persuasive to reduce (zurueckfuehren) history to the story which I tell from memory; but as I have pointed out, the telling, the story, die Erzaehlung, then itself becomes an experience, becomes something which is in turn remembered, which re-enforces, overlaps, and may even replace or mask the original. And beyond the story there are the concurring reports from other tellers of stories (historians), relating their experience of the signal event from their different perspective. There will be mementos, artifacts, pictures, paintings, drawings, photographs, which themselves become subjects of history, which add to the complexity and richness of the historical picture. There are, come to think of it, many species of "history". There are the accounts of purported glaciers, ice ages and volcanoes 500 million years ago; there are accounts of dinosaurs and other exotic animals, now long extinct, who have never been the subject of any individual's experience but whose existence is (merely) the inference of paleological studies. There is folklore which merges into history and there are myths too numerous to relate. There are the histories and gospels on which religious beliefs and practices are based. There are cosmological extrapolations of what "happened" in the universe uncounted light years ago. There are scientific "observations", past present and contemplated. There are reports of organizational, especially judicial proceedings, and there is the sworn judicial testimony of witnesses purporting to be the truth, the whole truth and nothing but the truth. All of this history makes claims to objective truth, claims which require to be reconciled with the hypothesis that all history, in essence, addresses memory, and that therefore the truth of all history is subjective. It is not possible to find, or to define, an algorithm that will do justice to the claims of each of these diverse histories to objective truth. One must proceed empirically, and for each history examine the evidence, the rationale, the conclusions and the claims of truth, to understand what they are about and how they should be interpreted. The one unifying factor which may provide a common denominator to all these claims of objective truth, is that in all cases, the story which is told, is told in words, words which are common to the hearers, words which are therefore elements of objectivity, subject to social assessment and comparison. The objective truth of the story which is told, cannot therefore relate to the experience, which is unique to each individual historian: It must relate to the (words of the) story itself, which by virtue of having been told has become public. That makes sense. It appears then that history, as the telling of experience, logicizes - if I may coin a word - that experience, makes it socially accessible and makes it, by that token, the subject of objective truth. Logic is a subset of mathematics and exhibits the same qualities of objective truth. The objective truth, to be sure (wohlbemerkt) is a quality of the account; it is not a quality of the experience which the account relates. As a corollary and in an appendix, one must consider the phenomena of fantasy, invention, lying and pathological lying. It seems that for various reasons, or none at all, one may invent or fabricate a story simulating experience, and leading the hearer, and perhaps oneself to be persuaded of the truth of ones invention. The conviction of subjective truth is appropriately and properly called faith; and it may be that it was the subjectivity of the truth of history which explains the predomenant role of faith in Luther's theology. Just as by virtue of its being expressed in language, history become susceptible to a degree of objective truth, so the natural sciences, as soon as they deviate or detach themselves from mathematics, become susceptible to a degree of subjective truth. In order to assess this propensity, one must closely scrutinize each science and interpret it accordung to its specific and peculiar characteristics. * * * * *

Zurueck - Back

Weiter - Next

2008 Index

Website Index

Copyright 2008, Ernst Jochen Meyer